اجازه ویرایش برای همه اعضا

حقیقت

نویسه گردانی: ḤQYQT
حقیقت مفهوم و اصطلاحی است برای اشاره به اصل هر چیز استفاده می‌شود[۱].
محتویات [نمایش]
واژه‌شناسی [ویرایش]

واژه حقیقت وام‌واژه‌ای است که از واژه عربی حقیقة وارد فارسی شده‌است. معادل انگلیسی واژه حقیقت واژهٔ Truth می‌باشد.
تفاوت حقیقت و واقعیت [ویرایش]

حقیقت شامل ذات هر چیزی بوده و غیر قابل تغییر است و به همین دلیل بر خلاف واقعیت امری است که لزوما با برهان‌های علمی قابل اثبات نیست. در بسیاری موارد حقیقت ( به دلیل اینکه از دسترس انسان به حیطه ذات به دور است )به نوع نگرش افراد بستگی پیدا میکند. بطور مثال واقعیت و حقیقت واقعه کربلا را می‌توان به این دو صورت بیان کرد.
واقعیت: حسین و یارانش به سمت کوفه حرکت کردند، لشکریان یزید در محلی به نام کربلا بر آنها حمله کردند، و حسین کشته شد. و یزید پیروز این جنگ بود.
اما حقیقت به عقیده یک راوی از این واقعیت می‌تواند این باشد:
در واقعه کربلا امام حسین و یاران با وفایش برای نجات دین اسلام تصمیم به هجرت به کوفه گرفتند. اما لشکریان یزید ملعون به آنان حمله کردند و در این واقعه امام حسین به شهادت رسید. و امام حسین توانست با نثار خون خود اسلام را زنده نگاه دارد و به حق او پیروز این میدان بود.
و یک راوی دیگر می‌تواند این طور آن را بیان کند:
حسین بن علی با سوء استفاده از نسبت خانوادگی خود با پیامبر با گروه اندکی فتنه‌گر برای محاربه با حضرت یزید خلیفهٔ مشروع مسلمین به کوفه حمله کرد. امپراتوری استکباری روم و باقی‌ماندهٔ سلطنت‌طلبان ایرانی و منافقین خوارج هم به حمایت از او پرداخته و به تفرقه در میان مسلمانان و ضعف نظام اسلامی امیدوار شده بودند. مردم کوفه که ابتدا تحت تأثیر سفسطه‌های او قرار گرفته بودند با خطبه‌های روشنگرانهٔ عبیدالله بن زیاد به حقیقت موضوع آگاه شده و حماسهٔ بصیرت آنان در روز عاشورا طومار حیات فتنه‌گران را درهم پیچید.
همانطور که می‌بینید برای اثبات واقعیت این موضوع می‌توان برهان‌هایی از جمله کتب تاریخ آورد. اما در مورد حقیقت نمی‌توان این کار را کرد. این به این معنی نیست که حقیقت چون همیشه اثبات پذیر نیست دارای درصد صحت کمی است زیرا امکان صحت آن همیشه وجود دارد.
اگر در ریشهٔ واژگان حقیقت و واقعیت دقیق شویم، تفاوت‌هایی را مشاهده می‌کنیم. ریشهٔ کلمهٔ حقیقت، "حق" به معنای راستی و درستی است و ریشهٔ کلمهٔ واقعیت، "وَقَعَ" به معنای رویدادن و یا اتفاق افتادن است. حقیقت، اشاره به ماهیت راست و درست دارد و واقعیت اشاره به امور عینی و یا اموری که اتفاق می‌افتند.
یک نگرش افراطی حقیقت یک واقعه تاریخی را جز بیان عواطف و احساسات گوینده در رابطه با آن واقعه نمیداند.
حقیقت و واقعیت در اندیشه‌های متفکران و فلاسفه [ویرایش]
در یونان باستان، نوعی تفکر اسطوره‌ای نسبت به مقولهٔ حقیقت و واقعیت وجود داشته که طی سیر تحول به مذهب و باورهای مذهبی تبدیل شده است. این مساله در هر تمدن دیگری نیز مشاهده می‌شود. تمدن‌های بین‌النهرین، هند و چین همگی چنین سیر تحولی را طی کرده‌اند.
تفکر اسطوره‌ای، طی تکاملش به صورت مثالی افلاطونی رسید که گونه‌ای تفکر مذهبی است. در اندیشه‌های مذهبی مانند سه مذهب زرتشتیت، مسیحیت و اسلام تمایز و جدایی واقعیت مادی و حقیقت وجود دارد.
دیدگاه عرفا پیرامون حقیقت و واقعیت، شکل متکامل تفکرات دینی است.
آراء و اندیشه‌های متفکرین دوران مدرن و همچنین تحولاتی که در نوع نگاه انسان‌ها در جامعهٔ مدرن نسبت به حقیقت حاصل شده، باعث شده است تا مسیر گسست از اندیشه‌های اسطوره‌ای به اندیشه‌های دینی در دوران مدرن دچار واگشت و یا تغییر مسیر شود. یعنی تمایز و گسست حقیقت و واقعیت دوباره به اتحاد آن دو منجر شده است. در اصل، ظهور رئالیسم جدید و همچنین اومانیسم مدرن، نمایانگر گونه‌ای بازگشت به اصول کلاسیک یونانیان است. بشر در دوران مدرن اعتقاد یافت که طی سالیان درازی، دچار خطا شده است، از این رو دوباره به تفکر یونانی رجعت کرد.
در اندیشه‌های ماتریالیست‌ها و مارکسیست‌ها از جمله فوئرباخ، مارکس و انگلس و پیروان آن‌ها، ماده‌گرایی که خود یکی از ثمرات مدرنیته است، نمایشگر رجعت انسان به یکی انگاشتن حقیقت و واقعیت است. با این تفاوت که از نگاه ماتریالیست‌ها، حقایق، قوانینی هستند که بر واقعیات حاکم‌اند. به طور مثال، نیروی محرکهٔ تاریخ که بر وقایع تاریخی احاطه دارد، حقیقتی دربارهٔ جهان و هستی است.
اندیشه‌های فردریش ویلهلم نیچه، فیلسوف نامدار آلمانی دربارهٔ حقیقت از اهمیت بسیار بالایی برخوردار است. چون او، نوع نگاه انسان به حقیقت را دگرگون کرد و با وهمی خواندن حقیقت، به تبیین یک نگاه کاملا نسبی‌گرایانه پرداخت. نسبیت حقیقت که با نیچه آغاز شد در نهایت به مکاتب و تفکراتی از جمله هرمنوتیک، مکتب فرانکفورت و پست‌مدرنیسم منجر شد.
اندیشه‌های نسبی‌گرایانهٔ نیچه در باب حقیقت و واقعیت به شکلی رادیکال در آراء متفکران پست مدرنی چون ژان فرانسوا لیوتار، ژاک دریدا، ژیل دلوز، میشل فوکو و ژان بودریار دوباره مطرح شد. استاد ایلیا.م.رام الله نیز تفاوت حقیقت با واقعیت را اینگونه توصیف میکنند:« حقیقت بوده هست و خواهد بود. ازلی و ابدی است. لیکن واقعیت «بوده» اما شاید دیگر حالا نباشد. یا الان هست اما چه بسا بعدا نباشد و شاید هم نه در گذشته بوده و نه در حالا بلکه در «آینده» واقع شود. واقعیت «هست» است و حقیقت هستی «هست» است. هست جزیی از هستی است، اما هستی جزیی از هست نیست... حقیق زنده و حاضر است وانگهی لایتناهی و نامحدود است. اما واقعیت ممکن است چنین نباشد. که اگر بود جزیی از جریان حقیقت بود.
جستارهای وابسته [ویرایش]

واقعیت
منابع [ویرایش]

↑ معنی واژه حقیقت در فرهنگ معین
[نهفتن]
ن • ب • و
تصوف
مفاهیم
احسان نور مقام حال منزل یقین فنا بقاء حقیقت معرفت نفس سلوک لطائف سته
جهان بینی
کشف ماوراءالطبیعه روانشناسی تجلی فلسفه
شیوه‌های عملی
ذکر حضره مراقبه قوالی سماع
فرقه‌ها
چشتیه ملامتیان مولویه مریدیه نقشبندیه قادریه رفاعیه شاذلیه سهروردیه تیجانیه فهرست فرقه‌های تصوف
قدما
اویس قرنی معروف کرخی حارث محاسبی رابعه ابراهیم ادهم بایزید جنید شبلی سری سقطی ذوالنون حلاج ابوسعید ابوالخیر ابوحمزه خراسانی ابوعثمان حیری ابوحفص حداد ابوعثمان مغربی احمد بن حرب حبیب عجمی محمد غزالی خرقانی احمد رفاعی گیلانی معین‌الدین سهروردی بختیار کاکی بابافرید ابن عربی شمس تبریزی مولوی سعدی ابراهیم خواص عطار محمود شبستری نظام‌الدین اولیا علی هجویری نقشبند بخاری امیرخسرو دهلوی نصیرالدین چراغ دهلوی صفی‌الدین اردبیلی شاه نعمت‌الله ولی اسماعیل قصری نجم‌الدین کبری جامی شاه ولی‌الله ابن عطاءالله میر حیدر آملی علی احمد کلیاری احمد زروق احمد یسوی اشرف جهانگیر سمنانی احمد فاروقی بتائی امام حداد سلطان باهو سچل سرمست لال شهباز قلندر
معاصران تصوف
علی‌اکبر خانجانی عبدالحکیم مراد احمد علوی ناظم قبرسی هشام قبانی نوح حم کلر محمد مالکی عبدالقادر صوفی گوهرشاهی عنایت خان عظیمی هلمینسکی حائری یعقوبی بایراک طاهر قادری واگوان لی ادریس شاه دنیل موره
پژوهشگران
عقیلی آلمکویست بورکهارت چیتیک کربن ارنست فراگر گنون هیکسون لیندبوم نیکلسون لینگز نصر شیمل سلز شوئون لویزون صدوقی سها ابراهیمی دینانی یثربی موحد امین‌رضوی
جستارها
هنر تاریخ موسیقی شعر آرامگاه‌های صوفیان متون تصوف در نیشابور
رده‌ها: اصول اخلاقیچالش‌های اخلاقیراستگوییفلسفه سیاسیمفهوم‌ها در منطقمفهوم‌های فلسفیمنطقنظریه حقیقتواقعیت

قس عربی

الحقیقة تدل على عدة معان، فهی الصدق فی تعارضه مع الکذب، وهی الواقع فی تعارضه مع الوهم.فـ الحقیقة أحد الإشکالات الکبرى فی مجال نظریة المعرفة وفلسفة العلم. فحینما یؤکد المرء وجود أو حدوث أمر ما، فهو یعتبره حقیقیا. وفی هذا السیاق، تهتم فلسفة المعرفة بالبحث عن حلول للعدید من المسائل الفلسفیة المتعلقة بموضوع "الحقیقة".

أهم وأول المشکلات المطروحة دوما على الفلاسفة هی تحدید أی نوع من الأشیاء یعد حقیقیا وأیها زائف، أی غیر حقیقی. ولِمعالجة هذا الإشکال، توجد مجموعة کبیرة من النظریات حول ما یجعل الأشیاء "حقیقیة". وترى النظریات، التی توصف بالقویة، أن الحقیقة خاصیة، فی حین تصفها النظریات التفریغیة (Deflationary) بأنها لیست سوى وسیلة من وسائل اللغة. وتلقی التطورات الحدیثة فی المنطق الصوری کثیرا من الضوء على طریقة استعمال مصطلح حقیقة فی الأنساق الصوریة (المنطق والریاضیات) وفی اللغات الطبیعیة (الألسن المستعملة فی التداول الیومی).

هذه بذرة مقالة عن شخصیات أو مصطلحات متعلقة بالفلسفة تحتاج للنمو والتحسین، فساهم فی إثرائها بالمشارکة فی تحریرها.
تصنیفات: نظریة المعرفةفلسفةمفاهیم فلسفیةفلسفة سیاسیة

قس انگلیسی

Truth is most often used to mean in accord with fact or reality[1] or fidelity to an original or to a standard or ideal.[1]
The opposite of truth is falsehood, which, correspondingly, can also take on a logical, factual, or ethical meaning. The concept of truth is discussed and debated in several contexts, including philosophy and religion. Many human activities depend upon the concept, which is assumed rather than a subject of discussion, including science, law, and everyday life.
Various theories and views of truth continue to be debated among scholars and philosophers. Language and words are a means by which humans convey information to one another and the method used to recognize a "truth" is termed a criterion of truth. There are differing claims on such questions as what constitutes truth: what things are truthbearers capable of being true or false; how to define and identify truth; the roles that revealed and acquired knowledge play; and whether truth is subjective or objective, relative or absolute.
Many religions consider perfect knowledge of all truth about all things (omniscience) to be an attribute of a divine or supernatural being.
Contents [show]
[edit]Nomenclature, orthography, and etymology

Further information: Veritas, Aletheia, and Tryggvi
The English word truth is from Old English tríewþ, tréowþ, trýwþ, Middle English trewþe, cognate to Old High German triuwida, Old Norse tryggð. Like troth, it is a -th nominalisation of the adjective true (Old English tréowe).
The English word true is from Old English (West Saxon) (ge)tríewe, tréowe, cognate to Old Saxon (gi)trûui, Old High German (ga)triuwu (Modern German treu "faithful"), Old Norse tryggr, Gothic triggws,[2] all from a Proto-Germanic *trewwj- "having good faith". Old Norse trú, "faith, word of honour; religious faith, belief"[3] (archaic English troth "loyalty, honesty, good faith", compare Ásatrú).
Thus, 'truth' involves both the quality of "faithfulness, fidelity, loyalty, sincerity, veracity",[4] and that of "agreement with fact or reality", in Anglo-Saxon expressed by sōþ (Modern English sooth).
All Germanic languages besides English have introduced a terminological distinction between truth "fidelity" and truth "factuality". To express "factuality", North Germanic opted for nouns derived from sanna "to assert, affirm", while continental West Germanic (German and Dutch) opted for continuations of wâra "faith, trust, pact" (cognate to Slavic věra "(religious) faith", but influenced by Latin verus). Romance languages use terms following the Latin veritas, while the Greek aletheia, Russian pravda and Serbian istina have separate etymological origins.
[edit]Major theories of truth

The question of what is a proper basis for deciding how words, symbols, ideas and beliefs may properly be considered true, whether by a single person or an entire society, is dealt with by the five major substantive theories introduced below. Each theory presents perspectives that are widely shared by published scholars.[5][6][7] There also have more recently arisen "deflationary" or "minimalist" theories of truth based on the idea that the application of a term like true to a statement does not assert anything significant about it, for instance, anything about its nature, but that the label truth is a tool of discourse used to express agreement, to emphasize claims, or to form certain types of generalizations.[5][8][9]
[edit]Substantive theories
[edit]Correspondence theory
Main article: Correspondence theory of truth
Correspondence theories state that true beliefs and true statements correspond to the actual state of affairs.[10] This type of theory posits a relationship between thoughts or statements on one hand, and things or objects on the other. It is a traditional model which goes back at least to some of the classical Greek philosophers such as Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle.[11] This class of theories holds that the truth or the falsity of a representation is determined in principle solely by how it relates to "things", by whether it accurately describes those "things". An example of correspondence theory is the statement by the Thirteenth Century philosopher/theologian Thomas Aquinas: Veritas est adaequatio rei et intellectus ("Truth is the equation [or adequation] of things and intellect"), a statement which Aquinas attributed to the Ninth Century neoplatonist Isaac Israeli.[12][13] Aquinas also restated the theory as: "A judgment is said to be true when it conforms to the external reality"[14]
Correspondence theory practically operates on the assumption that truth is a matter of accurately copying what was much later called "objective reality" and then representing it in thoughts, words and other symbols.[15] Many modern theorists have stated that this ideal cannot be achieved independently of some analysis of additional factors.[5][16] For example, language plays a role in that all languages have words that are not easily translatable into another. The German word Zeitgeist is one such example: one who speaks or understands the language may "know" what it means, but any translation of the word apparently fails to accurately capture its full meaning (this is a problem with many abstract words, especially those derived in agglutinative languages). Thus, some words add an additional parameter to the construction of an accurate truth predicate. Among the philosophers who grappled with this problem is Alfred Tarski, whose semantic theory is summarized further below in this article.[17]
Proponents of several of the theories below have gone further to assert that there are yet other issues necessary to the analysis, such as interpersonal power struggles, community interactions, personal biases and other factors involved in deciding what is seen as truth.
[edit]Coherence theory
Main article: Coherence theory of truth


Walter Seymour Allward's Veritas (Truth) outside Supreme Court of Canada, Ottawa, Ontario Canada
For coherence theories in general, truth requires a proper fit of elements within a whole system. Very often, though, coherence is taken to imply something more than simple logical consistency; often there is a demand that the propositions in a coherent system lend mutual inferential support to each other. So, for example, the completeness and comprehensiveness of the underlying set of concepts is a critical factor in judging the validity and usefulness of a coherent system.[18] A pervasive tenet of coherence theories is the idea that truth is primarily a property of whole systems of propositions, and can be ascribed to individual propositions only according to their coherence with the whole. Among the assortment of perspectives commonly regarded as coherence theory, theorists differ on the question of whether coherence entails many possible true systems of thought or only a single absolute system.
Some variants of coherence theory are claimed to characterize the essential and intrinsic properties of formal systems in logic and mathematics.[19] However, formal reasoners are content to contemplate axiomatically independent and sometimes mutually contradictory systems side by side, for example, the various alternative geometries. On the whole, coherence theories have been criticized as lacking justification in their application to other areas of truth, especially with respect to assertions about the natural world, empirical data in general, assertions about practical matters of psychology and society, especially when used without support from the other major theories of truth.[20]
Coherence theories distinguish the thought of rationalist philosophers, particularly of Spinoza, Leibniz, and G.W.F. Hegel, along with the British philosopher F.H. Bradley.[21] They have found a resurgence also among several proponents of logical positivism, notably Otto Neurath and Carl Hempel.
[edit]Constructivist theory
Main article: Constructivist epistemology
Social constructivism holds that truth is constructed by social processes, is historically and culturally specific, and that it is in part shaped through the power struggles within a community. Constructivism views all of our knowledge as "constructed," because it does not reflect any external "transcendent" realities (as a pure correspondence theory might hold). Rather, perceptions of truth are viewed as contingent on convention, human perception, and social experience. It is believed by constructivists that representations of physical and biological reality, including race, sexuality, and gender are socially constructed.
Giambattista Vico was among the first to claim that history and culture were man-made. Vico's epistemological orientation gathers the most diverse rays and unfolds in one axiom – verum ipsum factum – "truth itself is constructed". Hegel and Marx were among the other early proponents of the premise that truth is, or can be, socially constructed. Marx, like many critical theorists who followed, did not reject the existence of objective truth but rather distinguished between true knowledge and knowledge that has been distorted through power or ideology. For Marx scientific and true knowledge is 'in accordance with the dialectical understanding of history' and ideological knowledge 'an epiphenomenal expression of the relation of material forces in a given economic arrangement'.[22]
[edit]Consensus theory
Main article: Consensus theory of truth
Consensus theory holds that truth is whatever is agreed upon, or in some versions, might come to be agreed upon, by some specified group. Such a group might include all human beings, or a subset thereof consisting of more than one person.
Among the current advocates of consensus theory as a useful accounting of the concept of "truth" is the philosopher Jürgen Habermas.[23] Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed upon in an ideal speech situation.[24] Among the current strong critics of consensus theory is the philosopher Nicholas Rescher.[25]
[edit]Pragmatic theory
Main article: Pragmatic theory of truth
The three most influential forms of the pragmatic theory of truth were introduced around the turn of the 20th century by Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. Although there are wide differences in viewpoint among these and other proponents of pragmatic theory, they hold in common that truth is verified and confirmed by the results of putting one's concepts into practice.[26]
Peirce defines truth as follows: "Truth is that concordance of an abstract statement with the ideal limit towards which endless investigation would tend to bring scientific belief, which concordance the abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its inaccuracy and one-sidedness, and this confession is an essential ingredient of truth."[27] This statement emphasizes Peirce's view that ideas of approximation, incompleteness, and partiality, what he describes elsewhere as fallibilism and "reference to the future", are essential to a proper conception of truth. Although Peirce uses words like concordance and correspondence to describe one aspect of the pragmatic sign relation, he is also quite explicit in saying that definitions of truth based on mere correspondence are no more than nominal definitions, which he accords a lower status than real definitions.
William James's version of pragmatic theory, while complex, is often summarized by his statement that "the 'true' is only the expedient in our way of thinking, just as the 'right' is only the expedient in our way of behaving."[28] By this, James meant that truth is a quality, the value of which is confirmed by its effectiveness when applying concepts to practice (thus, "pragmatic").
John Dewey, less broadly than James but more broadly than Peirce, held that inquiry, whether scientific, technical, sociological, philosophical or cultural, is self-corrective over time if openly submitted for testing by a community of inquirers in order to clarify, justify, refine and/or refute proposed truths.[29]
Though not widely publicized, a new variation of the pragmatic theory was defined and wielded successfully from the 20th century forward. Defined and named by William Ernest Hocking, this variation is known as "negative pragmatism". Essentially, what works may or may not be true, but what fails cannot be true because the truth always works.[30] Richard Feynman also ascribed to it: "We never are definitely right, we can only be sure we are wrong."[31] This approach incorporates many of the ideas from Peirce, James, and Dewey. For Peirce, the idea of "... endless investigation would tend to bring about scientific belief ..." fits negative pragmatism in that a negative pragmatist would never stop testing. As Feynman noted, an idea or theory "... could never be proved right, because tomorrow's experiment might succeed in proving wrong what you thought was right."[31] Similarly, James and Dewey's ideas also ascribe to repeated testing which is "self-corrective" over time.
Pragmatism and negative pragmatism are also closely aligned with the coherence theory of truth in that any testing should not be isolated but rather incorporate knowledge from all human endeavors and experience. The universe is a whole and integrated system, and testing should recognize and account for its diversity. As Feynman said, "... if it disagrees with experiment, it is wrong."[32]
[edit]Minimalist (deflationary) theories
Main article: Deflationary theory of truth
Some philosophers reject the thesis that the concept or term truth refers to a real property of sentences or propositions. These philosophers are responding, in part, to the common use of truth predicates (e.g., that some particular thing "...is true") which was particularly prevalent in philosophical discourse on truth in the first half of the 20th century. From this point of view, to assert the proposition "'2 + 2 = 4' is true" is logically equivalent to asserting the proposition "2 + 2 = 4", and the phrase "is true" is completely dispensable in this and every other context. These positions are broadly described
as deflationary theories of truth, since they attempt to deflate the presumed importance of the words "true" or truth,
as disquotational theories, to draw attention to the disappearance of the quotation marks in cases like the above example, or
as minimalist theories of truth.[5][33]
Whichever term is used, deflationary theories can be said to hold in common that "[t]he predicate 'true' is an expressive convenience, not the name of a property requiring deep analysis."[5] Once we have identified the truth predicate's formal features and utility, deflationists argue, we have said all there is to be said about truth. Among the theoretical concerns of these views is to explain away those special cases where it does appear that the concept of truth has peculiar and interesting properties. (See, e.g., Semantic paradoxes, and below.)
In addition to highlighting such formal aspects of the predicate "is true", some deflationists point out that the concept enables us to express things that might otherwise require infinitely long sentences. For example, one cannot express confidence in Michael's accuracy by asserting the endless sentence:
Michael says, 'snow is white' and snow is white, or he says 'roses are red' and roses are red or he says ... etc.
This assertion can also be succinctly expressed by saying: What Michael says is true.[34]
[edit]Performative theory of truth
Attributed to P. F. Strawson is the performative theory of truth which holds that to say "'Snow is white' is true" is to perform the speech act of signaling one's agreement with the claim that snow is white (much like nodding one's head in agreement). The idea that some statements are more actions than communicative statements is not as odd as it may seem. Consider, for example, that when the bride says "I do" at the appropriate time in a wedding, she is performing the act of taking this man to be her lawful wedded husband. She is not describing herself as taking this man, but actually doing so (perhaps the most thorough analysis of such "illocutionary acts" is J. L. Austin, "How to Do Things With Words"[35]).
Strawson holds that a similar analysis is applicable to all speech acts, not just illocutionary ones: "To say a statement is true is not to make a statement about a statement, but rather to perform the act of agreeing with, accepting, or endorsing a statement. When one says 'It's true that it's raining,' one asserts no more than 'It's raining.' The function of [the statement] 'It's true that...' is to agree with, accept, or endorse the statement that 'it's raining.'"[36]
[edit]Redundancy and related theories
Main article: Redundancy theory of truth
According to the redundancy theory of truth, asserting that a statement is true is completely equivalent to asserting the statement itself. For example, making the assertion that " 'Snow is white' is true" is equivalent to asserting "Snow is white". Redundancy theorists infer from this premise that truth is a redundant concept; that is, it is merely a word that is traditionally used in conversation or writing, generally for emphasis, but not a word that actually equates to anything in reality. This theory is commonly attributed to Frank P. Ramsey, who held that the use of words like fact and truth was nothing but a roundabout way of asserting a proposition, and that treating these words as separate problems in isolation from judgment was merely a "linguistic muddle".[5][37][38]
A variant of redundancy theory is the disquotational theory which uses a modified form of Tarski's schema: To say that '"P" is true' is to say that P. A version of this theory was defended by C. J. F. Williams in his book What is Truth?. Yet another version of deflationism is the prosentential theory of truth, first developed by Dorothy Grover, Joseph Camp, and Nuel Belnap as an elaboration of Ramsey's claims. They argue that sentences like "That's true", when said in response to "It's raining", are prosentences, expressions that merely repeat the content of other expressions. In the same way that it means the same as my dog in the sentence My dog was hungry, so I fed it, That's true is supposed to mean the same as It's raining — if you say the latter and I then say the former. These variations do not necessarily follow Ramsey in asserting that truth is not a property, but rather can be understood to say that, for instance, the assertion "P" may well involve a substantial truth, and the theorists in this case are minimalizing only the redundancy or prosentence involved in the statement such as "that's true."[5]
Deflationary principles do not apply to representations that are not analogous to sentences, and also do not apply to many other things that are commonly judged to be true or otherwise. Consider the analogy between the sentence "Snow is white" and the character named Snow White, both of which can be true in some sense. To a minimalist, saying "Snow is white is true" is the same as saying "Snow is white," but to say "Snow White is true" is not the same as saying "Snow White."
[edit]Pluralist theories
Main article: Pluralist theories of truth
Several of the major theories of truth hold that there is a particular property the having of which makes a belief or proposition true. Pluralist theories of truth assert that there may be more than one property that makes propositions true: ethical propositions might be true by virtue of coherence. Propositions about the physical world might be true by corresponding to the objects and properties they are about.
Some of the pragmatic theories, such as those by Charles Peirce and William James, included aspects of correspondence, coherence and constructivist theories.[27][28] Crispin Wright argued in his 1992 book Truth and Objectivity that any predicate which satisfied certain platitudes about truth qualified as a truth predicate. In some discourses, Wright argued, the role of the truth predicate might be played by the notion of superassertibility.[39] Michael Lynch, in a 2009 book Truth as One and Many, argued that we should see truth as a functional property capable of being multiply manifested in distinct properties like correspondence or coherence.[40]
[edit]Most believed theories
According to a survey of professional philosophers and others on their philosophical views which was carried out in November 2009 (taken by 3226 respondents, including 1803 philosophy faculty members and/or PhDs and 829 philosophy graduate students) 44.9% of respondents accept or lean towards correspondence theories, 20.7% accept or lean towards deflationary theories and 13.8% epistemic theories.[41]
[edit]Formal theories

[edit]Truth in logic
Main articles: Logical truth, Criteria of truth, and Truth value
Logic is concerned with the patterns in reason that can help tell us if a proposition is true or not. However, logic does not deal with truth in the absolute sense, as for instance a metaphysician does. Logicians use formal languages to express the truths which they are concerned with, and as such there is only truth under some interpretation or truth within some logical system.
A logical truth (also called an analytic truth or a necessary truth) is a statement which is true in all possible worlds[42] or under all possible interpretations, as contrasted to a fact (also called a synthetic claim or a contingency) which is only true in this world as it has historically unfolded. A proposition such as "If p and q, then p." is considered to be logical truth because it is true because of the meaning of the symbols and words in it and not because of any facts of any particular world. They are such that they could not be untrue.
[edit]Truth in mathematics
Main articles: Model theory and Proof theory
There are two main approaches to truth in mathematics. They are the model theory of truth and the proof theory of truth[citation needed].
Historically, with the nineteenth century development of Boolean algebra mathematical models of logic began to treat "truth", also represented as "T" or "1", as an arbitrary constant. "Falsity" is also an arbitrary constant, which can be represented as "F" or "0". In propositional logic, these symbols can be manipulated according to a set of axioms and rules of inference, often given in the form of truth tables.
In addition, from at least the time of Hilbert's program at the turn of the twentieth century to the proof of Gödel's incompleteness theorems and the development of the Church-Turing thesis in the early part of that century, true statements in mathematics were generally assumed to be those statements which are provable in a formal axiomatic system.[citation needed]
The works of Kurt Gödel, Alan Turing, and others shook this assumption, with the development of statements that are true but cannot be proven within the system.[43] Two examples of the latter can be found in Hilbert's problems. Work on Hilbert's 10th problem led in the late twentieth century to the construction of specific Diophantine equations for which it is undecidable whether they have a solution,[44] or even if they do, whether they have a finite or infinite number of solutions. More fundamentally, Hilbert's first problem was on the continuum hypothesis.[45] Gödel and Paul Cohen showed that this hypothesis cannot be proved or disproved using the standard axioms of set theory.[46] In the view of some, then, it is equally reasonable to take either the continuum hypothesis or its negation as a new axiom.
[edit]Semantic theory of truth
Main article: Semantic theory of truth
The semantic theory of truth has as its general case for a given language:
'P' is true if and only if P
where 'P' is a reference to the sentence (the sentence's name), and P is just the sentence itself.
Logician and philosopher Alfred Tarski developed the theory for formal languages (such as formal logic). Here he restricted it in this way: no language could contain its own truth predicate, that is, the expression is true could only apply to sentences in some other language. The latter he called an object language, the language being talked about. (It may, in turn, have a truth predicate that can be applied to sentences in still another language.) The reason for his restriction was that languages that contain their own truth predicate will contain paradoxical sentences like the Liar: This sentence is not true. See The Liar paradox. As a result Tarski held that the semantic theory could not be applied to any natural language, such as English, because they contain their own truth predicates. Donald Davidson used it as the foundation of his truth-conditional semantics and linked it to radical interpretation in a form of coherentism.
Bertrand Russell is credited with noticing the existence of such paradoxes even in the best symbolic formalizations of mathematics in his day, in particular the paradox that came to be named after him, Russell's paradox. Russell and Whitehead attempted to solve these problems in Principia Mathematica by putting statements into a hierarchy of types, wherein a statement cannot refer to itself, but only to statements lower in the hierarchy. This in turn led to new orders of difficulty regarding the precise natures of types and the structures of conceptually possible type systems that have yet to be resolved to this day.
[edit]Kripke's theory of truth
Saul Kripke contends that a natural language can in fact contain its own truth predicate without giving rise to contradiction. He showed how to construct one as follows:
Begin with a subset of sentences of a natural language that contains no occurrences of the expression "is true" (or "is false"). So The barn is big is included in the subset, but not " The barn is big is true", nor problematic sentences such as "This sentence is false".
Define truth just for the sentences in that subset.
Then extend the definition of truth to include sentences that predicate truth or falsity of one of the original subset of sentences. So "The barn is big is true" is now included, but not either "This sentence is false" nor "'The barn is big is true' is true".
Next, define truth for all sentences that predicate truth or falsity of a member of the second set. Imagine this process repeated infinitely, so that truth is defined for The barn is big; then for "The barn is big is true"; then for "'The barn is big is true' is true", and so on.
Notice that truth never gets defined for sentences like This sentence is false, since it was not in the original subset and does not predicate truth of any sentence in the original or any subsequent set. In Kripke's terms, these are "ungrounded." Since these sentences are never assigned either truth or falsehood even if the process is carried out infinitely, Kripke's theory implies that some sentences are neither true nor false. This contradicts the Principle of bivalence: every sentence must be either true or false. Since this principle is a key premise in deriving the Liar paradox, the paradox is dissolved.[47]
[edit]Notable views



La Vérité "Truth" by Jules Joseph Lefebvre
[edit]Ancient history
The ancient Greek origins of the words "true" and "truth" have some consistent definitions throughout great spans of history that were often associated with topics of logic, geometry, mathematics, deduction, induction, and natural philosophy.
Socrates', Plato's and Aristotle's ideas about truth are commonly seen as consistent with correspondence theory. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle stated: "To say of what is that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true".[48] The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy proceeds to say of Aristotle:
"(...) Aristotle sounds much more like a genuine correspondence theorist in the Categories (12b11, 14b14), where he talks of "underlying things" that make statements true and implies that these "things" (pragmata) are logically structured situations or facts (viz., his sitting, his not sitting). Most influential is his claim in De Interpretatione (16a3) that thoughts are "likenessess" (homoiosis) of things. Although he nowhere defines truth in terms of a thought's likeness to a thing or fact, it is clear that such a definition would fit well into his overall philosophy of mind. (...)"[48]
Very similar statements can also be found in Plato (Cratylus 385b2, Sophist 263b).[48]
In Hinduism, Truth is defined as "unchangeable", "that which has no distortion", "that which is beyond distinctions of time, space, and person", "that which pervades the universe in all its constancy". Human body, therefore is not completely true as it changes with time, for example. There are many references, properties and explanations of truth by Hindu sages that explain varied facets of truth, such as "Satyam eva jayate" (Truth alone wins), "Satyam muktaye" (Truth liberates), "Satya' is 'Parahit'artham' va'unmanaso yatha'rthatvam' satyam" (Satya is the benevolent use of words and the mind for the welfare of others or in other words responsibilities is truth too), "When one is firmly established in speaking truth, the fruits of action become subservient to him ( patanjali yogasutras, sutra number 2.36 ), "The face of truth is covered by a golden bowl. Unveil it, O Pusan (Sun), so that I who have truth as my duty (satyadharma) may see it!" (Brhadaranyaka V 15 1-4 and the brief IIsa Upanisad 15-18), Truth is superior to silence (Manusmriti), etc. Combined with other words, satya acts as modifier, like "ultra" or "highest," or more literally "truest," connoting purity and excellence. For example, satyaloka is the "highest heaven' and Satya Yuga is the "golden age" or best of the four cyclical cosmic ages in Hinduism, and so on.
[edit]Medieval age
[edit]Avicenna
In early Islamic philosophy, Avicenna (Ibn Sina) defined truth in his Metaphysics of Healing, Book I, Chapter 8, as:
"What corresponds in the mind to what is outside it."[49]
Avicenna elaborated on his definition of truth in his Metaphysics Book Eight, Chapter 6:
"The truth of a thing is the property of the being of each thing which has been established in it."[50]
However, this definition is merely a translation of the Latin translation from the Middle Ages.[51] A modern translation of the original Arabic text states:
"Truth is also said of the veridical belief in the existence [of something]".[52]
[edit]Aquinas
Reevaluating Avicenna, and also Augustine and Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas stated in his Disputed Questions on Truth:
A natural thing, being placed between two intellects, is called true insofar as it conforms to either. It is said to be true with respect to its conformity with the divine intellect insofar as it fulfills the end to which it was ordained by the divine intellect... With respect to its conformity with a human intellect, a thing is said to be true insofar as it is such as to cause a true estimate about itself.[53]
Thus, for Aquinas, the truth of the human intellect (logical truth) is based on the truth in things (ontological truth).[54] Following this, he wrote an elegant re-statement of Aristotle's view in his Summa I.16.1:
Veritas est adæquatio intellectus et rei.
(Truth is the conformity of the intellect to the things.)
Aquinas also said that real things participate in the act of being of the Creator God who is Subsistent Being, Intelligence, and Truth. Thus, these beings possess the light of intelligibility and are knowable. These things (beings; reality) are the foundation of the truth that is found in the human mind, when it acquires knowledge of things, first through the senses, then through the understanding and the judgement done by reason. For Aquinas, human intelligence ("intus", within and "legere", to read) has the capability to reach the essence and existence of things because it has a non-material, spiritual element, although some moral, educational, and other elements might interfere with its capability.
[edit]Modern age
[edit]Kant


Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant endorses a definition of truth along the lines of the correspondence theory of truth.[48] Kant writes in the Critique of Pure Reason: "The nominal definition of truth, namely that it is the agreement of cognition with its object, is here granted and presupposed".[55] However, Kant denies that this correspondence definition of truth provides us with a test or criterion to establish which judgements are true. Kant states in his logic lectures:
:"(...) Truth, it is said, consists in the agreement of cognition with its object. In consequence of this mere nominal definition, my cognition, to count as true, is supposed to agree with its object. Now I can compare the object with my cognition, however, only by cognizing it. Hence my cognition is supposed to confirm itself, which is far short of being sufficient for truth. For since the object is outside me, the cognition in me, all I can ever pass judgement on is whether my cognition of the object agrees with my cognition of the object. The ancients called such a circle in explanation a diallelon. And actually the logicians were always reproached with this mistake by the sceptics, who observed that with this definition of truth it is just as when someone makes a statement before a court and in doing so appeals to a witness with whom no one is acquainted, but who wants to establish his credibility by maintaining that the one who called him as witness is an honest man. The accusation was grounded, too. Only the solution of the indicated problem is impossible without qualification and for every man. (...)"[56]
This passage makes use of his distinction between nominal and real definitions. A nominal definition explains the meaning of a linguistic expression. A real definition describes the essence of certain objects and enable us to determine whether any given item falls within the definition.[57] Kant holds that the definition of truth is merely nominal and, therefore, we cannot employ it to establish which judgements are true. According to Kant, the ancient skeptics criticized the logicians for holding that, by means of a merely nominal definition of truth, they can establish which judgements are true. They were trying to do something that is "impossible without qualification and for every man".[56]
[edit]Hegel
Georg Hegel distanced his philosophy from psychology by presenting truth as being an external self–moving object instead of being related to inner, subjective thoughts. Hegel's truth is analogous to the mechanics of a material body in motion under the influence of its own inner force. "Truth is its own self–movement within itself."[58] Teleological truth moves itself in the three–step form of dialectical triplicity toward the final goal of perfect, final, absolute truth. For Hegel, the progression of philosophical truth is a resolution of past oppositions into increasingly more accurate approximations to absolute truth. Chalybäus used the terms "thesis", "antithesis", and "synthesis" to describe Hegel's dialectical triplicity. The "thesis" consists of an incomplete historical movement. To resolve the incompletion, an "antithesis" occurs which opposes the "thesis." In turn, the "synthesis" appears when the "thesis" and "antithesis" become reconciled and a higher level of truth is obtained. This "synthesis" thereby becomes a "thesis," which will again necessitate an "antithesis," requiring a new "synthesis" until a final state is reached as the result of reason's historical movement. History is the Absolute Spirit moving toward a goal. This historical progression will finally conclude itself when the Absolute Spirit understands its own infinite self at the very end of history. Absolute Spirit will then be the complete expression of an infinite God.
[edit]Schopenhauer
For Arthur Schopenhauer,[59] a judgment is a combination or separation of two or more concepts. If a judgment is to be an expression of knowledge, it must have a sufficient reason or ground by which the judgment could be called true. Truth is the reference of a judgment to something different from itself which is its sufficient reason (ground). Judgments can have material, formal, transcendental, or metalogical truth. A judgment has material truth if its concepts are based on intuitive perceptions that are generated from sensations. If a judgment has its reason (ground) in another judgment, its truth is called logical or formal. If a judgment, of, for example, pure mathematics or pure science, is based on the forms (space, time, causality) of intuitive, empirical knowledge, then the judgment has transcendental truth.
[edit]Kierkegaard
When Søren Kierkegaard, as his character Johannes Climacus, ends his writings: My thesis was, subjectivity, heartfelt is the truth, he does not advocate for subjectivism in its extreme form (the theory that something is true simply because one believes it to be so), but rather that the objective approach to matters of personal truth cannot shed any light upon that which is most essential to a person's life. Objective truths are concerned with the facts of a person's being, while subjective truths are concerned with a person's way of being. Kierkegaard agrees that objective truths for the study of subjects like mathematics, science, and history are relevant and necessary, but argues that objective truths do not shed any light on a person's inner relationship to existence. At best, these truths can only provide a severely narrowed perspective that has little to do with one's actual experience of life.[60]
While objective truths are final and static, subjective truths are continuing and dynamic. The truth of one's existence is a living, inward, and subjective experience that is always in the process of becoming. The values, morals, and spiritual approaches a person adopts, while not denying the existence of objective truths of those beliefs, can only become truly known when they have been inwardly appropriated through subjective experience. Thus, Kierkegaard criticizes all systematic philosophies which attempt to know life or the truth of existence via theories and objective knowledge about reality. As Kierkegaard claims, human truth is something that is continually occurring, and a human being cannot find truth separate from the subjective experience of one's own existing, defined by the values and fundamental essence that consist of one's way of life.[61]
[edit]Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche believed the search for truth or 'the will to truth' was a consequence of the will to power of philosophers. He thought that truth should be used as long as it promoted life and the will to power, and he thought untruth was better than truth if it had this life enhancement as a consequence. As he wrote in Beyond Good and Evil, "The falseness of a judgment is to us not necessarily an objection to a judgment... The question is to what extent it is life-advancing, life-preserving, species-preserving, perhaps even species-breeding..." (aphorism 4). He proposed the will to power as a truth only because according to him it was the most life affirming and sincere perspective one could have.
Robert Wicks discusses Nietzsche's basic view of truth as follows:
"(...) Some scholars regard Nietzsche's 1873 unpublished essay, "On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense" ("Über Wahrheit und Lüge im außermoralischen Sinn") as a keystone in his thought. In this essay, Nietzsche rejects the idea of universal constants, and claims that what we call "truth" is only "a mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, and anthropomorphisms." His view at this time is that arbitrariness completely prevails within human experience: concepts originate via the very artistic transference of nerve stimuli into images; "truth" is nothing more than the invention of fixed conventions for merely practical purposes, especially those of repose, security and consistence. (...)"[62]
[edit]Whitehead
Alfred North Whitehead, a British mathematician who became an American philosopher[citation needed], said: "There are no whole truths; all truths are half-truths. It is trying to treat them as whole truths that play the devil".
The logical progression or connection of this line of thought is to conclude that truth can lie, since half-truths are deceptive and may lead to a false conclusion.
[edit]Nishida
According to Kitaro Nishida, "knowledge of things in the world begins with the differentiation of unitary consciousness into knower and known and ends with self and things becoming one again. Such unification takes form not only in knowing but in the valuing (of truth) that directs knowing, the willing that directs action, and the feeling or emotive reach that directs sensing."[63]
[edit]Fromm
Erich Fromm finds that trying to discuss truth as "absolute truth" is sterile and that emphasis ought to be placed on "optimal truth". He considers truth as stemming from the survival imperative of grasping one's environment physically and intellectually, whereby young children instinctively seek truth so as to orient themselves in "a strange and powerful world". The accuracy of their perceived approximation of the truth will therefore have direct consequences on their ability to deal with their environment. Fromm can be understood to define truth as a functional approximation of reality. His vision of optimal truth is described partly in "Man from Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics" (1947), from which excerpts are included below.
the dichotomy between 'absolute = perfect' and 'relative = imperfect' has been superseded in all fields of scientific thought, where "it is generally recognized that there is no absolute truth but nevertheless that there are objectively valid laws and principles".
In that respect, "a scientifically or rationally valid statement means that the power of reason is applied to all the available data of observation without any of them being suppressed or falsified for the sake of a desired result". The history of science is "a history of inadequate and incomplete statements, and every new insight makes possible the recognition of the inadequacies of previous propositions and offers a springboard for creating a more adequate formulation."
As a result "the history of thought is the history of an ever-increasing approximation to the truth. Scientific knowledge is not absolute but optimal; it contains the optimum of truth attainable in a given historical period." Fromm furthermore notes that "different cultures have emphasized various aspects of the truth" and that increasing interaction between cultures allows for these aspects to reconcile and integrate, increasing further the approximation to the truth.
[edit]Foucault


Quod Est Veritas? Christ and Pilate, by Nikolai Ge
Truth, says Michel Foucault, is problematic when any attempt is made to see truth as an "objective" quality. He prefers not to use the term truth itself but "Regimes of Truth". In his historical investigations he found truth to be something that was itself a part of, or embedded within, a given power structure. Thus Foucault's view shares much in common with the concepts of Nietzsche. Truth for Foucault is also something that shifts through various episteme throughout history.[64]
[edit]Baudrillard
Jean Baudrillard considered truth to be largely simulated, that is pretending to have something, as opposed to dissimulation, pretending to not have something. He took his cue from iconoclasts who he claims knew that images of God demonstrated that God did not exist.[65] Baudrillard wrote in "Precession of the Simulacra":
The simulacrum is never that which conceals the truth—it is the truth which conceals that there is none. The simulacrum is true.
—Ecclesiastes[66][67]
Some examples of simulacra that Baudrillard cited were: that prisons simulate the "truth" that society is free; scandals (e.g., Watergate) simulate that corruption is corrected; Disney simulates that the U.S. itself is an adult place. One must remember that though such examples seem extreme, such extremity is an important part of Baudrillard's theory. For a less extreme example, consider how movies usually end with the bad being punished, humiliated, or otherwise failing, thus affirming for viewers the concept that the good end happily and the bad unhappily, a narrative which implies that the status quo and institutionalised power structures are largely legitimate.[65]
[edit]In medicine and psychiatry

There is controversy as to the truth value of a proposition made in bad faith self-deception, such as when a hypochondriac has a complaint with no physical symptom.[68]
[edit]In religion: omniscience

Main article: Omniscience
In a religious context, perfect knowledge of all truth about all things (omniscience) is regarded by some religions, particularly Buddhism and the Abrahamic religions (Christianity, Islam, and Judaism), as an attribute of a divine being.[69] In the Abrahamic view, God can exercise divine judgment, judging the dead on the basis of perfect knowledge of their lives.[70][71]
[edit]See also

Thinking portal

Book: Epistemology
Wikipedia books are collections of articles that can be downloaded or ordered in print.
Aletheia
Asha
Belief
Confirmation holism
Contextualism
Contradiction
Degrees of truth
Disposition
Eclecticism
Imagination
Independence
Interpretation
Invariance
Lie
Normative science
Perspectivism
Physical symbol system
Public opinion
Relativism
Religious truth
Satya
Slingshot argument
Statistical independence
Tautology (logic)
Tautology (rhetoric)
Truth prevails
Truthiness
Truthlikeness
Two truths doctrine
Unity of the proposition
Verisimilitude
Veritas
What is truth?
[edit]Major theorists
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
J.L. Austin
Brand Blanshard
John Dewey
Hartry Field
Gottlob Frege
Jürgen Habermas
G. W. F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Augustine of Hippo
Paul Horwich
William James
Harold Joachim
Saul Kripke
Friedrich Nietzsche
Charles Sanders Peirce
Plato
Karl Popper
W.V. Quine
Frank P. Ramsey
Bertrand Russell
Arthur Schopenhauer
Socrates
P.F. Strawson
Alfred Tarski
Ludwig Wittgenstein
[edit]Notes

^ a b Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionary, truth, 2005
^ see Holtzmann's law for the -ww- : -gg- alternation.
^ A Concise Dictionary of Old Icelandic, Geir T. Zoëga (1910), Northvegr.org
^ OED on true has "Steadfast in adherence to a commander or friend, to a principle or cause, to one's promises, faith, etc.; firm in allegiance; faithful, loyal, constant, trusty; Honest, honourable, upright, virtuous, trustworthy; free from deceit, sincere, truthful " besides "Conformity with fact; agreement with reality; accuracy, correctness, verity; Consistent with fact; agreeing with the reality; representing the thing as it is; Real, genuine; rightly answering to the description; properly so called; not counterfeit, spurious, or imaginary."
^ a b c d e f g Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Supp., "Truth", auth: Michael Williams, p572-573 (Macmillan, 1996)
^ Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK. Includes papers by James, Ramsey, Russell, Tarski, and more recent work.
^ Hale, Bob; Wright, Crispin, eds. (1999). A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. pp. 309–330. doi:10.1111/b.9780631213260.1999.00015.x. edit
^ Horwich, Paul, Truth, (2nd edition, 1988),
^ Field, Hartry, Truth and the Absence of Fact (2001).
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, p223 (Macmillan, 1969) Prior uses Bertrand Russell's wording in defining correspondence theory. According to Prior, Russell was substantially responsible for helping to make correspondence theory widely known under this name.
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, pp. 223-224 (Macmillan, 1969)
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, p224, Macmillan, 1969.
^ "Correspondence Theory of Truth", in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
^ "Correspondence Theory of Truth", in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (citing De Veritate Q.1, A.1&3; cf. Summa Theologiae Q.16).
^ See, e.g., Bradley, F.H., "On Truth and Copying", in Blackburn, et al. (eds., 1999),Truth, 31-45.
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, pp. 223 ff. Macmillan, 1969. See especially, section on "Moore's Correspondence Theory", 225-226, "Russell's Correspondence Theory", 226-227, "Remsey and Later Wittgenstein", 228-229, "Tarski's Semantic Theory", 230-231.
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, p. 223 ff. Macmillan, 1969). See the section on "Tarski's Semantic Theory", 230-231.
^ Immanuel Kant, for instance, assembled a controversial but quite coherent system in the early 19th century, whose validity and usefulness continues to be debated even today. Similarly, the systems of Leibniz and Spinoza are characteristic systems that are internally coherent but controversial in terms of their utility and validity.
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Coherence Theory of Truth", auth: Alan R. White, p130-131 (Macmillan, 1969)
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Coherence Theory of Truth", auth: Alan R. White, p131-133, see esp., section on "Epistemological assumptions" (Macmillan, 1969)
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Coherence Theory of Truth", auth: Alan R. White, p130
^ May, Todd, 1993, Between Genealogy and Epistemology: Psychology, politics in the thought of Michel Foucault' with reference to Althusser and Balibar, 1970
^ See, e.g., Habermas, Jürgen, Knowledge and Human Interests (English translation, 1972).
^ See, e.g., Habermas, Jürgen, Knowledge and Human Interests (English translation, 1972), esp. PART III, pp 187 ff.
^ Rescher, Nicholas, Pluralism: Against the Demand for Consensus (1995).
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.5, "Pragmatic Theory of Truth", 427 (Macmillan, 1969).
^ a b Peirce, C.S. (1901), "Truth and Falsity and Error" (in part), pp. 716–720 in James Mark Baldwin, ed., Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, v. 2. Peirce's section is entitled "Logical", beginning on p. 718, column 1, and ending on p. 720 with the initials "(C.S.P.)", see Google Books Eprint. Reprinted, Collected Papers v. 5, pp. 565–573.
^ a b James, William, The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism', (1909).
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Dewey, John", auth Richard J. Bernstein, p383 (Macmillan, 1969)
^ Sahakian, W.S. & Sahakian, M.L., Ideas of the Great Philosophers, NEW YORK: Barnes & Noble, 1966, LCCCN 66-23155
^ a b Feynman, The Character of Physical Law, NEW YORK: Random House, 1994, ISBN 0-679-60127-9.
^ Feynman, The Character of Physical Law, p. 150.
^ Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth in the Introductory section of the book.
^ Kirkham, Theories of Truth, MIT Press, 1992.
^ J. L. Austin, "How to Do Things With Words". Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975
^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.6: Performative Theory of Truth, auth: Gertrude Ezorsky, p. 88 (Macmillan, 1969)
^ Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7, 153–170. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1990
^ Le Morvan, Pierre. (2004) "Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey", The British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12(4), pp. 705-718.
^ Truth and Objectivity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992.
^ Truth as One and Many (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
^ "Philpapers.org". Philpapers.org. Retrieved 2012-05-27.
^ Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
^ See, e.g., Chaitin, Gregory L., The Limits of Mathematics (1997) esp. 89 ff.
^ M. Davis. "Hilbert's Tenth Problem is Unsolvable." American Mathematical Monthly 80, pp. 233-269, 1973
^ Yandell, Benjamin H.. The Honors Class. Hilbert's Problems and Their Solvers (2002).
^ Chaitin, Gregory L., The Limits of Mathematics (1997) 1-28, 89 ff.
^ Kripke, Saul. "Outline of a Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy, 72 (1975), 690-716
^ a b c d David, Marion (2005). "Correspondence Theory of Truth" in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
^ Osman Amin (2007), "Influence of Muslim Philosophy on the West", Monthly Renaissance 17 (11).
^ Jan A. Aertsen (1988), Nature and Creature: Thomas Aquinas's Way of Thought, p. 152. BRILL, ISBN 90-04-08451-7.
^ Simone van Riet (in Latin). Liber de philosophia prima, sive Scientia divina. p. 413.
^ Avicenna: The Metaphysics of The Healing. Michael E. Marmura. Brigham Young University Press. 2005. p. 284. ISBN 0-934893-77-2.
^ Disputed Questions on Truth, 1, 2, c, reply to Obj. 1. Trans. Mulligan, McGlynn, Schmidt, Truth, vol. I, pp. 10-12.
^ "Veritas supra ens fundatur" (Truth is founded on being). Disputed Questions on Truth, 10, 2, reply to Obj. 3.
^ Kant, Immanuel (1781/1787), Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), A58/B82.
^ a b Kant, Immanuel (1801), The Jäsche Logic, in Lectures on Logic. Translated and edited by J. Michael Young (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 557-558.
^ Alberto Vanzo, "Kant on the Nominal Definition of Truth", Kant-Studien, 101 (2010), pp. 147-166.
^ "Die Wahrheit ist die Bewegung ihrer an ihr selbst." The Phenomenology of Spirit, Preface, ¶ 48
^ On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, §§ 29–33
^ Kierkegaard, Søren. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1992
^ Watts, Michael. Kierkegaard, Oxford: Oneworld Publications, 2003
^ Robert Wicks, Friedrich Nietzsche - Early Writings: 1872-1876, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
^ John Maraldo, Nishida Kitarô - Self-Awareness, in: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
^ Foucault, M. "The Order of Things", London: Vintage Books, 1970 (1966)
^ a b Jean Baudrillard. Simulacra and Simulation. Michigan: Michigan University Press, 1994.
^ Baudrillard, Jean. "Simulacra and Simulations", in Selected Writings, ed. Mark Poster, Stanford University Press, 1988) 166 ff
^ Baudrillard's attribution of this quote to Ecclesiastes is deliberately fictional. "Baudrillard attributes this quote to Ecclesiastes. However, the quote is a fabrication (see Jean Baudrillard. Cool Memories III, 1991-95. London: Verso, 1997). Editor's note: In Fragments: Conversations With François L'Yvonnet. New York: Routledge, 2004:11, Baudrillard acknowledges this 'Borges-like' fabrication." Cited in footnote #4 in Smith, Richard G., "Lights, Camera, Action: Baudrillard and the Performance of Representations", International Journal of Baudrillard Studies, Volume 2, Number 1 (January 2005)
^ "Absent a lesion or a physiological disturbance to account readily for the complaint, the complaint was likely to be regarded as male fide", Post-Modern Reflections on the Ethics of Naming, The Ethics of Diagnosis Philosophy and Medicine, 1992, Volume 40, Section V, 275-300, George Khushf, springerlink.com
^ Catholic Encyclopedia "The Nature and Attributes of God" http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/06612a.htm#IID
^ Catholic Encyclopedia, "Particular judgment" http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/08550a.htm
^ The Ancient Egyptians thought that there was a last judgement by the gods similar in many ways to the Abrahamic one, but instead of omniscient knowledge of truth, the life of the dead person was evaluated by Weighing of the Heart, which would record good and bad deeds.
[edit]References

Aristotle, "The Categories", Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 1–109 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1938.
Aristotle, "On Interpretation", Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 111–179 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1938.
Aristotle, "Prior Analytics", Hugh Tredennick (trans.), pp. 181–531 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1938.
Aristotle, "On the Soul" (De Anima), W. S. Hett (trans.), pp. 1–203 in Aristotle, Volume 8, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1936.
Audi, Robert (ed., 1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1995. 2nd edition, 1999. Cited as CDP.
Baldwin, James Mark (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 volumes in 4, Macmillan, New York, NY.
Baylis, Charles A. (1962), "Truth", pp. 321–322 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
Benjamin, A. Cornelius (1962), "Coherence Theory of Truth", p. 58 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK. Includes papers by James, Ramsey, Russell, Tarski, and more recent work.
Chandrasekhar, Subrahmanyan (1987), Truth and Beauty. Aesthetics and Motivations in Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
Chang, C.C., and Keisler, H.J., Model Theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam, Netherlands, 1973.
Chomsky, Noam (1995), The Minimalist Program, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Church, Alonzo (1962a), "Name Relation, or Meaning Relation", p. 204 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
Church, Alonzo (1962b), "Truth, Semantical", p. 322 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
Clifford, W.K. (1877), "The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays". (Prometheus Books, 1999), infidels.org
Dewey, John (1900–1901), Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901, Donald F. Koch (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL.
Dewey, John (1932), Theory of the Moral Life, Part 2 of John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics, Henry Holt and Company, New York, NY, 1908. 2nd edition, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1932. Reprinted, Arnold Isenberg (ed.), Victor Kestenbaum (pref.), Irvingtion Publishers, New York, NY, 1980.
Dewey, John (1938), Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938),Holt and Company, New York, NY. Reprinted, John Dewey, The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 12: 1938, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1986.
Field, Hartry (2001), Truth and the Absence of Fact, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
Foucault, Michel (1997), Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, Volume 1, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, Paul Rabinow (ed.), Robert Hurley et al. (trans.), The New Press, New York, NY.
Garfield, Jay L., and Kiteley, Murray (1991), Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, Paragon House, New York, NY.
Gupta, Anil (2001), "Truth", in Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, UK.
Haack, Susan (1993), Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, UK.
Habermas, Jürgen (1976), "What Is Universal Pragmatics?", 1st published, "Was heißt Universalpragmatik?", Sprachpragmatik und Philosophie, Karl-Otto Apel (ed.), Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. Reprinted, pp. 1–68 in Jürgen Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society, Thomas McCarthy (trans.), Beacon Press, Boston, MA, 1979.
Habermas, Jürgen (1990), Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen (trans.), Thomas McCarthy (intro.), MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Habermas, Jürgen (2003), Truth and Justification, Barbara Fultner (trans.), MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Hegel, Georg, (1977), Phenomenology of Spirit, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, ISBN 0-19-824597-1.
Horwich, Paul, (1988), Truth, 2nd edition, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
James, William (1904), A World of Pure Experience.
James, William (1907), Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular Lectures on Philosophy, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
James, William (1909), The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism', Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
James, William (1912), Essays in Radical Empiricism. Cf. Chapt. 3, "The Thing and its Relations", pp. 92–122.
Kant, Immanuel (1800), Introduction to Logic. Reprinted, Thomas Kingsmill Abbott (trans.), Dennis Sweet (intro.), Barnes and Noble, New York, NY, 2005.
Kirkham, Richard L. (1992), Theories of Truth, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Kneale, W., and Kneale, M. (1962), The Development of Logic, Oxford University Press, London, UK, 1962. Reprinted with corrections, 1975.
Kreitler, Hans, and Kreitler, Shulamith (1972), Psychology of the Arts, Duke University Press, Durham, NC.
Le Morvan, Pierre (2004), "Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey", British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 12 (4) 2004, 705–718, PDF.
Peirce, C.S., Bibliography.
Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as CP vol.para.
Peirce, C.S. (1877), "The Fixation of Belief", Popular Science Monthly 12 (1877), 1–15. Reprinted (CP 5.358–387), (CE 3, 242–257), (EP 1, 109–123). Eprint.
Peirce, C.S. (1901), "Truth and Falsity and Error" (in part), pp. 718–720 in J.M. Baldwin (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, vol. 2. Reprinted, CP 5.565–573.
Polanyi, Michael (1966), The Tacit Dimension, Doubleday and Company, Garden City, NY.
Quine, W.V. (1956), "Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes", Journal of Philosophy 53 (1956). Reprinted, pp. 185–196 in Quine (1976), Ways of Paradox.
Quine, W.V. (1976), The Ways of Paradox, and Other Essays, 1st edition, 1966. Revised and enlarged edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1976.
Quine, W.V. (1980 a), From a Logical Point of View, Logico-Philosophical Essays, 2nd edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Quine, W.V. (1980 b), "Reference and Modality", pp. 139–159 in Quine (1980 a), From a Logical Point of View.
Rajchman, John, and West, Cornel (ed., 1985), Post-Analytic Philosophy, Columbia University Press, New York, NY.
Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7, 153–170. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1990.
Ramsey, F.P. (1990), Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Rawls, John (2000), Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, Barbara Herman (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Rorty, R. (1979), Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Russell, Bertrand (1912), The Problems of Philosophy, 1st published 1912. Reprinted, Galaxy Book, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 1959. Reprinted, Prometheus Books, Buffalo, NY, 1988.
Russell, Bertrand (1918), "The Philosophy of Logical Atomism", The Monist, 1918. Reprinted, pp. 177–281 in Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950, Robert Charles Marsh (ed.), Unwin Hyman, London, UK, 1956. Reprinted, pp. 35–155 in The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, David Pears (ed.), Open Court, La Salle, IL, 1985.
Russell, Bertrand (1956), Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950, Robert Charles Marsh (ed.), Unwin Hyman, London, UK, 1956. Reprinted, Routledge, London, UK, 1992.
Russell, Bertrand (1985), The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, David Pears (ed.), Open Court, La Salle, IL.
Schopenhauer, Arthur, (1974), On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, Open Court, La Salle, IL, ISBN 0-87548-187-6.
Smart, Ninian (1969), The Religious Experience of Mankind, Charles Scribner's Sons, New York, NY.
Tarski, A., Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J.H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1956. 2nd edition, John Corcoran (ed.), Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN, 1983.
Wallace, Anthony F.C. (1966), Religion: An Anthropological View, Random House, New York, NY.
Reference works
Audi, Robert (ed., 1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1995. 2nd edition, 1999. Cited as CDP.
Blackburn, Simon (1996), The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1994. Paperback edition with new Chronology, 1996. Cited as ODP.
Runes, Dagobert D. (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ, 1962.
Webster's New International Dictionary of the English Language, Second Edition, Unabridged (1950), W.A. Neilson, T.A. Knott, P.W. Carhart (eds.), G. & C. Merriam Company, Springfield, MA. Cited as MWU.
Webster's Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary (1983), Frederick C. Mish (ed.), Merriam–Webster Inc., Springfield, MA. Cited as MWC.
[edit]External links

Wikiquote has a collection of quotations related to: Truth
Look up truth in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
Wikimedia Commons has media related to: Truth
An Introduction to Truth by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
Truth
Coherence theory of truth
Correspondence theory of truth
Deflationary theory of truth
Identity theory of truth
Revision theory of truth
Tarski's definition of truth
Axiomatic theories of truth
Heidegger on Truth (Aletheia) as Unconcealment
History of Truth: The Greek "Aletheia"
History of Truth: The Latin "Veritas"
[hide] v t e
Theories of truth
Coherence Consensus Constructivist Correspondence Deflationary Epistemic Indefinability Pragmatic Redundancy Semantic
[show]
Links to related articles
Help improve this pageWhat's this?
Did you find what you were looking for?Yes No
Categories: Core issues in ethicsRealityTheories of truthPhilosophical conceptsPolitical philosophyEthical principlesPhilosophical logicConcepts in epistemologyConcepts in metaphysicsConcepts in logicVeracityMeaning (philosophy of language)
واژه های قبلی و بعدی
واژه های همانند
۱۴ مورد، زمان جستجو: ۰.۱۳ ثانیه
حقیقت . [ ح َقی ق َ ] (ع اِ) چیزی که بطور قطع و یقین ثابت است . حقیقت اسم است برای چیزی که در محل خود مستقر باشد. (از تعریفات جرجانی ). ...
حقیقت . [ ح َ قی ق َ ] (اِخ ) سیدشاه بن سیدعرب شاه . از علما و شعرای متأخر هندوستان است .وفات او در اوائل مائه ٔ سیزدهم بمدرس بوده است . او...
این واژه میتواند در معنای فلسفی‌ اش به واژه "روشنا" برگردان شود و با توجه به معنای مصدری آن میتواند به راحتی‌ از عهده ی کار بر آید.
این واژه عربی است و پارسی جایگزین اینهاست: ساتیا sâtiâ (سنسکریت: satya)، ارزک árzak، آمنگ ãmang (سغدی)، آمتیژیا ãmtižiâ (سغدی: ãmticiâ)، رسانسات rasân...
بی حقیقت . [ ح َ قی ق َ ] (ص مرکب ) ناراست و ناخالص . (آنندراج ). || بی وفا. || ناسپاس . || نمک بحرام . || بطور نادرستی . (ناظم الاطباء).
حقیقت جو. [ ح َ قی ق َ ] (نف مرکب ) حقیقت جوی . جویای حقیقت . طالب حقیقت .
حقیقت طلب . [ ح َ قی ق َ طَ ل َ ] (نف مرکب ) حقیقت جوی . طالب حقیقت . جوینده ٔ حقیقت .
حقیقت بین . [ ح َ قی ق َ ] (نف مرکب ) آنکه بحقایق امور بیناست : سخنی بی غرض از بنده ٔ مخلص بشنوای که منظور بزرگان حقیقت بینی .حافظ.
حقیقت طلبی . [ ح َ قی ق َ طَ ل َ ] (حامص مرکب ) فعل ِ طلبیدن حقیقت . حقیقت جوئی .
حقیقت جویی . [ ح َقی ق َ ] (حامص مرکب ) چگونگی حقیقت جوی . حقیقت طلبی .
« قبلی صفحه ۱ از ۲ ۲ بعدی »
نظرهای کاربران
نظرات ابراز شده‌ی کاربران، بیانگر عقیده خود آن‌ها است و لزوماً مورد تأیید پارسی ویکی نیست.
برای نظر دادن ابتدا باید به سیستم وارد شوید. برای ورود به سیستم روی کلید زیر کلیک کنید.